Proposition 14

If a first magnitude has to a second the same ratio as a third has to a fourth, and the first is greater than the third, then the second is also greater than the fourth; if equal, equal; and if less, less.

Let a first magnitude A have the same ratio to a second B as a third C has to a fourth D, and let A be greater than C.

I say that B is also greater than D.

java applet or image
V.8

Since A is greater than C, and B is another, arbitrary, magnitude, therefore A has to B a greater ratio than C has to B.

V.13

But A is to B as C is to D, therefore C has to D a greater ratio than C has to B.

V.10

But that to which the same has a greater ratio is less, therefore D is less than B, so that B is greater than D.

Similarly we can prove that, if A equals C, then B equals D, and, if A is less than C, then B is less than D.

Therefore, if a first magnitude has to a second the same ratio as a third has to a fourth, and the first is greater than the third, then the second is also greater than the fourth; if equal, equal; and if less, less.

Q.E.D.

Guide

The statement is that In this form all four magnitudes need to be of the same kind.

The alternate form of the proposition

Sometimes the alternate form of this proposition

if a : b = c : d and a >=< b, then c >=< d

is invoked. The alternate form is just the definition of proportion, V.Def.5,

a : b = c : d means for numbers n and m that na >=< mb, implies nc >=< md

when n and m are both 1. There is some slippage in the meaning of number as used in the Elements; sometimes 1 is included as a number, but other times it is not and 2 is the smallest number. Convenience often forces convention, and it’s convenient to include 1 as a number.

This other form is more general since a and b may be of one kind while c and d can be of a different kind. (See definition V.Def.12 and proposition V.16 for alternate proportions.) For example, in proposition VI.25 there are the statements:

First, the proportion is converted to its alternate form by V.16. Then, it is claimed that since the first equals the second, therefore the third equals the fourth. Clearly, V.14 is not being invoked otherwise the alternate form of the proportion would not be mentioned.

Another example comes from X.112.

Here the first is greater than the second, so the third is greater than the fourth. Proposition VI.16 (if the rectangle contained by the extremes equals the rectangle contained by the means, then the four straight lines are proportional) was used to derive the proportion CB : BD = G : EF from the equality of the rectangles, but it would have been just as easy to conclude CB : G = BD : EF, and then V.14 could be used.

Clearly, this proposition V.14 is not being invoked in either of these propositions, but the alternate form is used instead.

Although this alternate form does not rely on using V.Def.4 as an axiom of comparability, the original form does. The statement of the proposition is false when infinitesimals are allowed. For a particular example, take the proportion x:(x + y) = x: (x + 2y) or its inverse.

Use of this proposition

This proposition is used in V.16 and a few other propositions in Books V, VI, X, XII, and XIII.